Freely generated algebraic structure over a given signature
In universal algebra and mathematical logic, a term algebra is a freely generated algebraic structure over a given signature.[1][2] For example, in a signature consisting of a single binary operation, the term algebra over a set X of variables is exactly the free magma generated by X. Other synonyms for the notion include absolutely free algebra and anarchic algebra.[3]
From a category theory perspective, a term algebra is the initial object for the category of all X-generated algebras of the same signature, and this object, unique up to isomorphism, is called an initial algebra; it generates by homomorphic projection all algebras in the category.[4][5]
A similar notion is that of a Herbrand universe in logic, usually used under this name in logic programming,[6] which is (absolutely freely) defined starting from the set of constants and function symbols in a set of clauses. That is, the Herbrand universe consists of all ground terms: terms that have no variables in them.
An atomic formula or atom is commonly defined as a predicate applied to a tuple of terms; a ground atom is then a predicate in which only ground terms appear. The Herbrand base is the set of all ground atoms that can be formed from predicate symbols in the original set of clauses and terms in its Herbrand universe.[7][8] These two concepts are named after Jacques Herbrand.
Term algebras also play a role in the semantics of abstract data types, where an abstract data type declaration provides the signature of a multi-sorted algebraic structure and the term algebra is a concrete model of the abstract declaration.
Universal algebra
A type
is a set of function symbols, with each having an associated arity (i.e. number of inputs). For any non-negative integer
, let
denote the function symbols in
of arity
. A constant is a function symbol of arity 0.
Let
be a type, and let
be a non-empty set of symbols, representing the variable symbols. (For simplicity, assume
and
are disjoint.) Then the set of terms
of type
over
is the set of all well-formed strings that can be constructed using the variable symbols of
and the constants and operations of
. Formally,
is the smallest set such that:
— each variable symbol from
is a term in
, and so is each constant symbol from
.
- For all
and for all function symbols
and terms
, we have the string
— given
terms
, the application of an
-ary function symbol
to them represents again a term.
The term algebra
of type
over
is, in summary, the algebra of type
that maps each expression to its string representation. Formally,
is defined as follows:[9]
- The domain of
is
.
- For each nullary function
in
,
is defined as the string
.
- For all
and for each n-ary function
in
and elements
in the domain,
is defined as the string
.
A term algebra is called absolutely free because for any algebra
of type
, and for any function
,
extends to a unique homomorphism
, which simply evaluates each term
to its corresponding value
. Formally, for each
:
- If
, then
.
- If
, then
.
- If
where
and
, then
.
Example
As an example type inspired from integer arithmetic can be defined by
,
,
, and
for each
.
The best-known algebra of type
has the natural numbers as its domain and interprets
,
,
, and
in the usual way; we refer to it as
.
For the example variable set
, we are going to investigate the term algebra
of type
over
.
First, the set
of terms of type
over
is considered.
We use red color to flag its members, which otherwise may be hard to recognize due to their uncommon syntactic form.
We have e.g.
, since
is a variable symbol;
, since
is a constant symbol; hence
, since
is a 2-ary function symbol; hence, in turn,
since
is a 2-ary function symbol.
More generally, each string in
corresponds to a mathematical expression built from the admitted symbols and written in Polish prefix notation;
for example, the term
corresponds to the expression
in usual infix notation. No parentheses are needed to avoid ambiguities in Polish notation; e.g. the infix expression
corresponds to the term
.
To give some counter-examples, we have e.g.
, since
is neither an admitted variable symbol nor an admitted constant symbol;
, for the same reason,
, since
is a 2-ary function symbol, but is used here with only one argument term (viz.
).
Now that the term set
is established, we consider the term algebra
of type
over
.
This algebra uses
as its domain, on which addition and multiplication need to be defined.
The addition function
takes two terms
and
and returns the term
; similarly, the multiplication function
maps given terms
and
to the term
.
For example,
evaluates to the term
.
As an example for unique extendability of a homomorphism consider
defined by
and
.
Informally,
defines an assignment of values to variable symbols, and once this is done, every term from
can be evaluated in a unique way in
.
For example,

In a similar way, one obtains
.
Herbrand base
The signature σ of a language is a triple <O, F, P> consisting of the alphabet of constants O, function symbols F, and predicates P. The Herbrand base[10] of a signature σ consists of all ground atoms of σ: of all formulas of the form R(t1, ..., tn), where t1, ..., tn are terms containing no variables (i.e. elements of the Herbrand universe) and R is an n-ary relation symbol (i.e. predicate). In the case of logic with equality, it also contains all equations of the form t1 = t2, where t1 and t2 contain no variables.
Decidability
Term algebras can be shown decidable using quantifier elimination. The complexity of the decision problem is in NONELEMENTARY because binary constructors are injective and thus pairing functions.[11]